β
Reading list (1972 edition)[edit]
1. Homer β Iliad, Odyssey
2. The Old Testament
3. Aeschylus β Tragedies
4. Sophocles β Tragedies
5. Herodotus β Histories
6. Euripides β Tragedies
7. Thucydides β History of the Peloponnesian War
8. Hippocrates β Medical Writings
9. Aristophanes β Comedies
10. Plato β Dialogues
11. Aristotle β Works
12. Epicurus β Letter to Herodotus; Letter to Menoecus
13. Euclid β Elements
14. Archimedes β Works
15. Apollonius of Perga β Conic Sections
16. Cicero β Works
17. Lucretius β On the Nature of Things
18. Virgil β Works
19. Horace β Works
20. Livy β History of Rome
21. Ovid β Works
22. Plutarch β Parallel Lives; Moralia
23. Tacitus β Histories; Annals; Agricola Germania
24. Nicomachus of Gerasa β Introduction to Arithmetic
25. Epictetus β Discourses; Encheiridion
26. Ptolemy β Almagest
27. Lucian β Works
28. Marcus Aurelius β Meditations
29. Galen β On the Natural Faculties
30. The New Testament
31. Plotinus β The Enneads
32. St. Augustine β On the Teacher; Confessions; City of God; On Christian Doctrine
33. The Song of Roland
34. The Nibelungenlied
35. The Saga of Burnt NjΓ‘l
36. St. Thomas Aquinas β Summa Theologica
37. Dante Alighieri β The Divine Comedy;The New Life; On Monarchy
38. Geoffrey Chaucer β Troilus and Criseyde; The Canterbury Tales
39. Leonardo da Vinci β Notebooks
40. NiccolΓ² Machiavelli β The Prince; Discourses on the First Ten Books of Livy
41. Desiderius Erasmus β The Praise of Folly
42. Nicolaus Copernicus β On the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres
43. Thomas More β Utopia
44. Martin Luther β Table Talk; Three Treatises
45. FranΓ§ois Rabelais β Gargantua and Pantagruel
46. John Calvin β Institutes of the Christian Religion
47. Michel de Montaigne β Essays
48. William Gilbert β On the Loadstone and Magnetic Bodies
49. Miguel de Cervantes β Don Quixote
50. Edmund Spenser β Prothalamion; The Faerie Queene
51. Francis Bacon β Essays; Advancement of Learning; Novum Organum, New Atlantis
52. William Shakespeare β Poetry and Plays
53. Galileo Galilei β Starry Messenger; Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences
54. Johannes Kepler β Epitome of Copernican Astronomy; Concerning the Harmonies of the World
55. William Harvey β On the Motion of the Heart and Blood in Animals; On the Circulation of the Blood; On the Generation of Animals
56. Thomas Hobbes β Leviathan
57. RenΓ© Descartes β Rules for the Direction of the Mind; Discourse on the Method; Geometry; Meditations on First Philosophy
58. John Milton β Works
59. MoliΓ¨re β Comedies
60. Blaise Pascal β The Provincial Letters; Pensees; Scientific Treatises
61. Christiaan Huygens β Treatise on Light
62. Benedict de Spinoza β Ethics
63. John Locke β Letter Concerning Toleration; Of Civil Government; Essay Concerning Human Understanding;Thoughts Concerning Education
64. Jean Baptiste Racine β Tragedies
65. Isaac Newton β Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy; Optics
66. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz β Discourse on Metaphysics; New Essays Concerning Human Understanding;Monadology
67. Daniel Defoe β Robinson Crusoe
68. Jonathan Swift β A Tale of a Tub; Journal to Stella; Gulliver's Travels; A Modest Proposal
69. William Congreve β The Way of the World
70. George Berkeley β Principles of Human Knowledge
71. Alexander Pope β Essay on Criticism; Rape of the Lock; Essay on Man
72. Charles de Secondat, baron de Montesquieu β Persian Letters; Spirit of Laws
73. Voltaire β Letters on the English; Candide; Philosophical Dictionary
74. Henry Fielding β Joseph Andrews; Tom Jones
75. Samuel Johnson β The Vanity of Human Wishes; Dictionary; Rasselas; The Lives of the Poets
β
β
Mortimer J. Adler (How to Read a Book: The Classic Guide to Intelligent Reading)
β
The end of law is not to abolish or restrain, but to preserve and enlarge freedom.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government)
β
Methinks Sir Robert should have carried his Monarchical Power one step higher and satisfied the World, that Princes might eat their Subjects too.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government)
β
The great question which in all ages has disturbed mankind, and brought on them the greatest part of those mischiefs which have ruined cities, depopulated countries, and disordered the peace of the world, has been, not whether there be power in the world, nor whence it came, but who should have it.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration)
β
Hence it is a mistake to think, that the supreme or legislative power of any common-wealth, can do what it will, and dispose of the estates of the subject arbitrarily, or take any part of them at pleasure.
β
β
John Locke (The Two Treatises of Civil Government)
β
Books seem to me to be pestilent things, and infect all that trade in them β¦ with something very perverse and brutal. Printers, binders, sellers, and others that make a trade and gain out of them have universally so odd a turn and corruption of mind, that they have a way of dealing peculiar to themselves, and not conformed to the good of society, and that general fairness that cements mankind.
β
β
John Locke (Locke: Two Treatises of Government (Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought))
β
I therefore took it into my hands with all the expectation and read it through with all the attention due to a Treaties, that made such a noise at its coming abroad and cannot but confess my self mightily surprised, that in a Book which was to provide Chains for all Mankind, I should find nothing but a Rope of Sand, useful perhaps to such, whose Skill and Business it is to raise a Dust, and would blind the People, the better to mislead them, but in truth is not of any force to draw those into Bondage, who have their Eyes open, and so much Sense about them as to consider, that Chains are but an Ill wearing, how much Care soever hath been taken to file and polish them.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government)
β
Freedom of Men under Government, is, to have a standing Rule to live by, common to every one of that Society, and made by the Legislative Power erected in it; A Liberty to follow my own Will in all things, where the Rule prescribes not; and not to be subject to the inconstant, uncertain, unknown, Arbitrary Will of another Man.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government)
β
in truth not of any force to draw those into bondage who have their eyes open,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
That all government is absolute monarchy."
And the ground he builds on is this,
"That no man is born free.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
We are all born slaves, and we must continue so;
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
governments must be left again to the old way of being made by contrivance and the consent of men
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
Dominion of life and death, making war, and concluding peace, p. 13. Adam and the patriarchs had absolute power of life and death,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
Kings are above the laws,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
Though it be ever so plain, that there ought to be government in the world,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
submission to government be every one's duty,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
man can never be obliged in conscience to submit to any power, unless he can be satisfied who is the person who has a right to exercise that power over him.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
nay, a right not only to a bare subsistence, but to the conveniencies and comforts of life, as far as the conditions of their parents can afford it.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
If kings, who are not heirs to Adam, have no right to sovereignty, we are all free,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
his principles could not be made to agree with that constitution and order which God had settled in the world,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
or a man's own consent subjects him to a superior.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
To speak less learnedly, and more intelligibly,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
not by the force of arguments and opposition, but by the intricacy of the words,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
since it would always be a sin, in any man of estate, to let his brother perish
for want of affording him relief out of his plenty.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
Children, I confess, are not born in this state of equality, though they are born to it.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
and by laws within themselves settled the properties of those of the same society
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
though this can scarce happen amongst that part of mankind that have consented to the use of money.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
we consult reason or revelation,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
It being by him removed from the common state nature hath placed it in, it hath by this labour something annexed to it that excludes the common right of other men.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
at least where there is enough, and as good, left in common for others.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
and the ore I have digged in any place, where I have a right to them in common with others
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
And amongst those who are counted the civilized part of mankind,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
As much land as a man tills, plants, improves, cultivates, and can use the product of, so much is his property.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
He that had as good left for his improvement as was already taken up, needed not complain, ought not to meddle with what was already improved by another's labour:
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
where there is no law, there is no freedom;
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
positive laws of an established government.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
gold, silver, and diamonds, are things that fancy or agreement hath put the value on, more than real use,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
He was only to look that he used them before they spoiled, else he took more than his share, and robbed others.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
the state of war once begun, continues with a right to the innocent party to destroy the other whenever he can, until the aggressor offers peace,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
without any express compact of all the commoners.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
the law of the land, which is not to be violated.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
king of a large and fruitful territory there feeds, lodges, and is clad worse than a day-labourer in England.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
for a man, not having the power of his own life, cannot, by compact, or his own consent, enslave himself to any one,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
we find among the Jews, as well as other nations, that men did sell themselves; but, it is plain, this was only to drudgery, not to slavery:
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
the case of land and water, where there is enough of both, is perfectly the same.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
govern his actions according to the dictates of the law of reason which God had implanted in him.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
nobody can be under a law which is not promulgated to him;
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
that, however it may be mistaken, the end of law is not to abolish or restrain, but to preserve and
enlarge freedom:
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
that every man should have as much as he could make use of, would hold still in the world, without straitening any body;
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
though men had a right to appropriate, by their labour, each one to himself, as much of
the things of nature as he could use:
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
thus it is that every man, in the state of nature, has a power to kill a murderer, both to deter others from doing the like injury, which no reparation can compensate,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
This makes it lawful for a man to kill a thief,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
we see how labour could make men distinct titles to several parcels of it, for their private uses; wherein there could be no doubt of right, no room for quarrel.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
It is no injury to call an half quotation an half reason.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government)
β
Chains are but an ill wearing, how much Care soever hath been taken to file and polish them.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government)
β
The end of Law is not to abolish or restrain, but to preserve and enlarge Freedom: For in all the states of created beings capable of Laws, where there is no law, there is no Freedom.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government)
β
distinction between pirates and lawful princes; he that has force is without any more ado to be obeyed, and crowns and sceptres would become the inheritance only of violence and rapine.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
justify to the world the people of England, whose love of their just and natural rights, with their resolution to preserve them, saved the nation when it was on the very brink of slavery and ruin.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
As much as any one can make use of to any advantage of life before it spoils, so much he may by his labour fix a property in: whatever is beyond this, is more than his share, and belongs to others.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
So that God, by commanding to subdue, gave authority so far to appropriate: and the condition of human life, which requires labour and materials to work on, necessarily introduces private possessions.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
And thus came in the use of money, some lasting thing that men might keep without spoiling, and that by mutual consent men would take in exchange for the truly useful, but perishable supports of life.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
had not the invention of money, and the tacit agreement of men to put a value on it, introduced (by consent) larger possessions, and a right to them; which, how it has done, I shall by and by show more at large.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
He that, in obedience to this command of God, subdued, tilled, and sowed any part of it, thereby annexed to it something
that was his property, which another had no title to, nor could without injury take from him.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
I take to be political power; that the power of a magistrate over a subject may be distinguished from that of a father over his children, a master over his servants, a husband over his wife, and a lord over his slave.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
God planted in men a strong desire also of propagating their kind, and continuing themselves in their posterity; and this gives children a title to share in the property of their parents, and a right to inherit their possessions.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
he, as much as he can, to preserve the rest of mankind, and may not, unless it be to do justice to an offender, take away or impair the life, or what tends to the preservation of life, the liberty, health, limb, or goods of another.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
God gave the world to men in common; but since he gave it them for their benefit, and the greatest conveniencies of life they were capable to draw from it, it cannot be supposed he meant it should always remain common and uncultivated.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
having by his fault forfeited his own life, by some act that deserves death; he, to whom he has forfeited it, may (when he has him in his power) delay to take it, and make use of him to his own service, and he does him no injury by it:
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
it will destroy the authority of the present governors, and absolve the people from subjection to them, since they, having no better claim than others to that power, which is alone the fountain of all authority, can have no title to rule over them.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
all parents were, by the law of nature, "under an obligation to preserve, nourish, and educate the children" they had begotten; not as their own workmanship, but the workmanship of their own maker, the Almighty, to whom they were to be accountable for them.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
Nay, the extent of ground is of so little value, without labour, that I have heard it affirmed, that in Spain itself a man may be permitted to plough, sow, and reap, without being disturbed, upon land he has no other title to, but only his making use of it.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
When any such declaration of God's intention is produced, it will be our duty to believe God intends it so; but till that be done, our author must show us some better warrant, before we shall be obliged to receive him as the authentic revealer of God's intentions.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
The state of nature has a law of nature to govern it, which obliges every one: and reason, which is that law, teaches all mankind, who will but consult it, that being all equal and independent, no one ought to harm another in his life, health, liberty, or possessions:
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
Freedom, then, is not what sir Robert Filmer tells us, O.A. 55, " a liberty for every one to do what he lists, to live as he pleases, and not to be tied by any laws :" but freedom of men under government is, to have a standing rule to live by, common to every one of the society,
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
To avoid this state of war (wherein there is no appeal but to Heaven, and wherein every the least difference is apt to end, where there is no authority to decide between the contenders) is one great reason of men's putting themselves into society, and quitting the state of nature:
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
equality which all men are in, in respect of jurisdiction or dominion one over another; which was the equality I there spoke of, as proper to the business in hand, being that equal right that every man hath to his natural freedom, without being subjected to the will or authority of any other man.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
flatter princes with an opinion, that they have a divine right to absolute power, let the laws by which they are constituted and are to govern, and the conditions under which they enter upon their authority, be what they will ; and their engagements to observe them ever so well ratified by solemn oaths and promises.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
Adam's children, being not presently as soon as born under this law of reason, were not presently free : for law, in its true notion, is not so much the limitation, as the direction of a free and intelligent agent to his proper interest, and prescribes no farther than is for the general good of those under that law:
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
Political power, then, I take to be a right of making laws with penalties of death, and consequently all less penalties, for the regulating and preserving of property, and of employing the force of the community, in the execution of such laws, and in the defence of the commonwealth from foreign injury; and all this only for the public good.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
To understand political power right, and derive it from its original, we must consider what state all men are naturally in, and that is, a state of perfect freedom to order their actions and dispose of their possessions and persons, as they think fit, within the bounds of the law of nature; without asking leave, or depending upon the will of any other man.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
but freedom is not, as we are told, " a liberty for every man to do what he lists:" (for who could be free, when every other man's humour might domineer over him ?) but a liberty to dispose and order as he lists his person, actions, possessions, and his whole property, within the allowance of those laws under which he is, and therein not to be subject to the arbitrary will of another, but freely follow his own.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
Right and conveniency went together; for as a man had a right to all he could employ his labour upon, so he had no temptation to labour for more than he could make use of. This left no room for controversy about the title, nor for encroachment on the right of others ; what portion a man carved to himself was easily seen: and it was useless, as well as dishonest, to carve himself too much, or take more than he needed.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
I think it will be but a very modest computation to say, that of the products of the earth useful to the life of man, nine-tenths are the effects of labour: nay, if we will rightly estimate things as they come to our use, and cast up the several expenses about them, what in them is purely owing to nature, and what to labour, we shall find, that in most of them ninety-nine hundredths are wholly to be put on the account of labour.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
have here rated the improved land very low, in making its product but as ten to one, when it is much nearer an hundred to one : for I ask, whether in the wild woods and uncultivated waste of America, left to nature, without any improvement, tillage, or husbandry, a thousand acres yield the needy and wretched inhabitants as many conveniencies of life as ten acres equally fertile land do in Devonshire, where they are well cultivated?
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
From all which it is evident, that though the things of nature are given in common, yet man, by being master of himself, and " proprietor of his own person, and the actions or labour of it, had still in himself the great foundation of property;" and that which made up the greater part of what he applied to the support or comfort of his being, when invention and arts had improved the conveniencies of life, was perfectly his own, and did not belong in common to others.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
This shows how much numbers of men are to be preferred to largeness of dominions ; and that the increase of lands, and the right of employing of them, is the great art of government: and that prince, who shall be so wise and godlike, as by established laws of liberty to secure protection and encouragement to the honest industry of mankind, against the oppression of power and narrowness of party, will quickly be too hard for his neighbours: but this by the by. To return to the argument in hand.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
The measure of property nature has well set by the extent of men's labour and the conveniencies of life: no man's labour could subdue, or appropriate all; nor could his enjoyment consume more than a small part; so that it was impossible for any man, this way, to intrench upon the right of another, or acquire to himself a property, to the prejudice of his neighbour, who would still have room for as good and as large a possession (after the other had taken out his) as before it was appropriated.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
to one who, even after the reading of sir Robert's book, cannot but think himself, as the laws allow him, a free man: and I know no fault it is to do so, unless
any one, better skilled in the fate of it than I, should have it revealed to him that this treatise, which has lain dormant so long, was, when it appeared in the world, to carry, by strength of its arguments, all liberty out of it; and that, from thenceforth, our author's short model was to be the pattern in the mount, and the perfect standard of politics for the future.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
government being for the preservation of every man's right and property, by preserving him from the violence or injury of others, is for the good of the governed : for the magistrate's sword being for a "terror to evil doers," and by that terror to enforce men to observe the positive laws of the society, made conformable to the laws of nature, for the public good, i. e. the good of every particular member of that society, as far as by common rules it can be provided for; the sword is not given the magistrate for his own good alone.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
Should any one make so perverse an use of God's blessings poured on him with a liberal hand; should any one be cruel and uncharitable to that extremity; yet all this would not prove that propriety in land, even in this case, gave any authority over the persons of men, but only that compact might; since the authority of the rich proprietor, and the subjection of the needy beggar, began not from the possession of the lord, but the consent of the poor man, who preferred being his subject to starving. And the man he thus submits to, can pretend to no more power over him than he has consented to, upon compact.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
that all men may be restrained from invading others' rights, and
from doing hurt to one another, and the law of nature be observed, which willeth the peace and preservation of all mankind, the execution of the law of nature is, in that state, put into every man's hands, whereby every one has a right to punish the transgressors of that law to such a degree as may hinder its violation: for the law of nature would, as all other laws that concern men in this world, be in vain, if there were nobody that in the state of nature had a power to execute that law, and thereby preserve the innocent, and restrain offenders.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
in The Leviathan, a treatise in which he concluded that the state of nature is a state of war, βof every man against every man.β20 Miraculously, the colony recovered; its population grew and its economy thrived with a new crop, tobacco, a plant found only in the New World and long cultivated by the natives.21 With tobacco came the prospect of profit, and a new political and economic order: the colonists would rule themselves and they would rule over others. In July 1619, twenty-two English colonists, two men from each of eleven parts of the colony, met in a legislative body, the House of Burgesses, the first self-governing body in the colonies.
β
β
Jill Lepore (These Truths: A History of the United States)
β
To narrow natural rights to such neat slogans as "liberty, equality, fraternity" or "life, liberty, property," . . . was to ignore the complexity of public affairs and to leave out of consideration most moral relationships. . . .
Burke appealed back beyond Locke to an idea of community far warmer and richer than Locke's or Hobbes's aggregation of individuals. The true compact of society, Burke told his countrymen, is eternal: it joins the dead, the living, and the unborn. We all participate in this spiritual and social partnership, because it is ordained of God. In defense of social harmony, Burke appealed to what Locke had ignored: the love of neighbor and the sense of duty. By the time of the French Revolution, Locke's argument in the Second Treatise already had become insufficient to sustain a social order. . . .
The Constitution is not a theoretical document at all, and the influence of Locke upon it is negligible, although Locke's phrases, at least, crept into the Declaration of Independence, despite Jefferson's awkwardness about confessing the source of "life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness."
If we turn to the books read and quoted by American leaders near the end of the eighteenth century, we discover that Locke was but one philosopher and political advocate among the many writers whose influence they acknowledged. . . .
Even Jefferson, though he had read Locke, cites in his Commonplace Book such juridical authorities as Coke and Kames much more frequently. As Gilbert Chinard puts it, "The Jeffersonian philosophy was born under the sign of Hengist and Horsa, not of the Goddess Reason"--that is, Jefferson was more strongly influenced by his understanding of British history, the Anglo-Saxon age particularly, than by the eighteenth-century rationalism of which Locke was a principal forerunner. . . .
Adams treats Locke merely as one of several commendable English friends to liberty. . . .
At bottom, the thinking Americans of the last quarter of the eighteenth century found their principles of order in no single political philosopher, but rather in their religion. When schooled Americans of that era approved a writer, commonly it was because his books confirmed their American experience and justified convictions they held already. So far as Locke served their needs, they employed Locke. But other men of ideas served them more immediately.
At the Constitutional Convention, no man was quoted more frequently than Montesquieu. Montesquieu rejects Hobbes's compact formed out of fear; but also, if less explicitly, he rejects Locke's version of the social contract. . . . It is Montesquieu's conviction that . . . laws grow slowly out of people's experiences with one another, out of social customs and habits. "When a people have pure and regular manners, their laws become simple and natural," Montesquieu says. It was from Montesquieu, rather than from Locke, that the Framers obtained a theory of checks and balances and of the division of powers. . . .
What Madison and other Americans found convincing in Hume was his freedom from mystification, vulgar error, and fanatic conviction: Hume's powerful practical intellect, which settled for politics as the art of the possible. . . . [I]n the Federalist, there occurs no mention of the name of John Locke. In Madison's Notes of Debates in the Federal Convention there is to be found but one reference to Locke, and that incidental. Do not these omissions seem significant to zealots for a "Lockean interpretation" of the Constitution? . . .
John Locke did not make the Glorious Revolution of 1688 or foreordain the Constitution of the United States. . . . And the Constitution of the United States would have been framed by the same sort of men with the same sort of result, and defended by Hamilton, Madison, and Jay, had Locke in 1689 lost the manuscripts of his Two Treatises of Civil Government while crossing the narrow seas with the Princess Mary.
β
β
Russell Kirk (Rights and Duties: Reflections on Our Conservative Constitution)
β
In transgressing the law of nature, the offender declares himself to live by another rule than that of reason and common equity, which is that measure God has set to the actions of men for their mutual security; and so he becomes dangerous to mankind, the tie, which is to secure them from injury and violence, being slighted and broken by him : which being a trespass against the whole species, and the peace and safety of it, provided for by the law of nature; every man upon this score, by the right he hath to preserve mankind in general, may restrain, or, where it is necessary, destroy things noxious to them, and so may bring such evil on any one, who hath transgressed that law, as may make him repent the doing of it, and thereby deter him, and by his example others, from doing the like mischief.
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
In transgressing the law of nature, the offender declares himself to live by another rule than that of reason and common equity, which is that measure God has set to the actions of men for their mutual security; and so he becomes dangerous to mankind, the tie, which is to secure them from injury and violence, being slighted and broken by him : which being a trespass against the whole species, and the peace and safety of it, provided for by the law of nature; every man upon this score, by the right he hath to preserve mankind in general, may restrain, or, where it is necessary, destroy things noxious to them, and so may bring such evil on any one, who hath transgressed that law, as may make him repent the doing of it, and thereby deter him, and by his example others, from doing the like mischief. And
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
easily grant, that civil government is the proper remedy for the inconveniencies of the state of nature, which must certainly be great, where men may be judges in their own case; since it is easy to be imagined, that he who was so unjust as to do his brother an injury, will scarce be so just as to condemn himself for it: but I shall desire those who make this objection to remember, that absolute monarchs are but men; and if government is to be the remedy of those evils, which necessarily follow from men's being j udges in their own cases, and the state of nature is therefore not to be endured ; I desire to know what kind of government that is, and how much better it is than the state of nature, where one man, commanding a multitude, has the liberty to be judge in his own case, and may do to all his subjects whatever he pleases, without the least liberty to any one to question or control those who execute his pleasure?
β
β
John Locke (Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Rethinking the Western Tradition))
β
The Russian goal was to quickly harness the power of personal access that social media gives and craft metanarratives and distribute in such a way that the enemy population can be turned against their own government. Opinion polls, news coverage, and street talk can be shifted by changing the perception of the populace. Social media not only weaponizes opinion, it gives the attacker the ability to act as puppeteer for an entire foreign nation. Two Russian information warfare officers wrote a treatise describing the combat effects of weaponized news and social media: βThe mass media today can stir up chaos and confusion in government and military management of any country and instill ideas of violence, treachery, and immorality, and demoralize the public. Put through this treatment, the armed forces personnel and public of any country will not be ready for active defense.β1 Additionally, the Russians make no distinction between using these activities in wartime and βpeace.β The Russian Federation will deploy information warfare and propaganda persistently in a constant effort to keep adversaries off balance. When it comes to information warfare, such distinctions of peacetime and wartime fade away.
β
β
Malcolm W. Nance (The Plot to Destroy Democracy: How Putin and His Spies Are Undermining America and Dismantling the West)
β
READABLE BY ANY CITIZEN This exhaustive textual analysis of the Second Amendment would never have been necessary in the nearly first two hundred years of the republic. It was only beginning in the second half of the twentieth century that the Orwellian view gained currency that βthe peopleβ means the states or state-conscripted militia, that βrightβ means governmental power, that βkeepβ does not mean to possess, that βbearβ does not mean carry, that βarmsβ do not include ordinary handguns and rifles, and that βinfringeβ does not include prohibition. But the Founders intended to, and did, word the Second Amendment in an easy to understand manner. Individuals have a right to have arms in their houses and to carry them, and the government may not violate that right. Recognition of the right promotes a militia composed of the body of the people, which is necessary for a free society. The Bill of Rights was intended to inform the ordinary citizen of his or her rights. Its meaning is not a monopoly of the governmental entities whose powers it was intended to limit. St. George Tucker said it best in his 1803 treatise, the first ever published on the Constitution, as follows: A bill of rights may be considered, not only as intended to give law, and assign limits to a government about to be established, but as giving information to the people. By reducing speculative truths to fundamental laws, every man of the meanest capacity and understanding may learn his own rights, and know when they are violated ....47 By knowing when oneβs rights are violated, the citizen may signify his or her displeasure through mechanisms such as the ballot box and the jury box, and may resort to speech, the press, assembly, and petition to denounce the evil. As the experiences of the American Revolution proved, the right to keep and bear arms serves as the ultimate check that the Founders hoped would dissuade persons at the helm of state from seeking to establish tyranny. In hindsight, it would be difficult to quarrel with the success of the Foundersβ vision.
β
β
Stephen P. Halbrook (The Founders' Second Amendment: Origins of the Right to Bear Arms (Independent Studies in Political Economy))
β
The Bible is relevant and real, and the people who inhabit its pages are people who have faced what you and I face. Life has disappointed them, others have disappointed them, and they have disappointed themselves. Just like us. Remarkably, amazingly and delightfully, these people are the people God uses. The disappointed ones. Sneaky and snarly people who often acted before they thought, who failed to act when they should have and sometimes didnβt act at all. Yet they were called friends of God. The man who named the people of Israel, Jacob, was a mamaβs boy. The one who became brave enough to stand up to his wealthy adopted family and side with the oppressed immigrant workers, Moses, lived with a stubborn insecurity. Rahab, a woman whose circumstances led to her prostituting herself, became the one who helped establish a country for the βpure and holyβ people of God. King David, famous for his devotion to God, gave into his voracious sexual appetites and passion. These are the ones God calls friends: people like the great prophet Elijah who struggled with depression, fear and a weird streak of pride that caused him to do an ugly power play over the fate of two little boys. Jonah, the prophet to the ancient city of Nineveh, who didnβt want to go because of his racism. John the Baptist, who would today likely be holed up in Idaho somewhere, living off his produce and writing treatises against the government and church.
β
β
Laura Sumner Truax (Undone: When Coming Apart Puts You Back Together)
β
Lockeβs Two Treatises of Government revealed that the political universe is run the same way, through natural laws that guide menβs behavior in the same sure way that they guide the movement of the planets.
β
β
Arthur Herman (The Cave and the Light: Plato Versus Aristotle, and the Struggle for the Soul of Western Civilization)