Oakeshott Quotes

We've searched our database for all the quotes and captions related to Oakeshott. Here they are! All 84 of them:

To be conservative, then, is to prefer the familiar to the unknown, to prefer the tried to the untried, fact to mystery, the actual to the possible, the limited to the unbounded, the near to the distant, the sufficient to the superabundant, the convenient to the perfect, present laughter to utopian bliss.
Michael Oakeshott (Rationalism in Politics and other essays)
Poetry is a sort of truancy, a dream within the dream of life, a wild flower planted among our wheat.
Michael Oakeshott
Like Midas, the Rationalist is always in the unfortunate position of not being able to touch anything, without transforming it into an abstraction; he can never get a square meal of experience.
Michael Oakeshott (Rationalism in Politics and other essays)
The rule of law bakes no bread, it is unable to distribute loaves or fishes (it has none), and it cannot protect itself against external assault, but it remains the most civilized and least burdensome conception of a state yet to be devised.
Michael Oakeshott (On history and other essays)
The man of conservative temperament believes that a known good is not lightly to be surrendered for an unknown better.
Michael Oakeshott (Rationalism in Politics and other essays)
In political activity . . . men sail a boundless and bottomless sea; there is neither harbour for shelter nor floor for anchorage, neither starting-place nor appointed destination. The enterprise is to keep afloat on an even keel; the sea is both friend and enemy, and the seamanship consists in using the resources of a traditional manner of behaviour in order to make a friend of every hostile occasion.
Michael Oakeshott (Rationalism in Politics and other essays)
I have wasted a lot of time living.
Michael Oakeshott
The conjunction of ruling and dreaming generates tyranny.
Michael Oakeshott
There is no wealth but life. Life, including all its powers of love, of joy, and of admiration. That country is the richest which nourishes the greatest number of noble and happy human beings.’ Ruskin
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
As civilized human beings, we are the inheritors, neither of an inquiry about ourselves and the world, nor of an accumulating body of information, but of a conversation, begun in the primeval forests and extended and made more articulate in the course of centuries. It is a conversation which goes on both in public and within each of ourselves.
Michael Oakeshott
A so-called ideal scheme which does not grow out of reality is definitely and finally not ideal at all.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
This, I believe, is the appropriate image of human intercourse -- appropriate because it recognizes the qualities, the diversities, and the proper relationships of human utterances. As civilized human beings, we are the inheritors, neither of an inquiry about ourselves and the world, nor of an accumulating body of information, but of a conversation, begun in the primeval forests and extended and made more articulate in the course of centuries. It is a conversation which goes on both in public and within each of ourselves.
Michael Oakeshott (Rationalism in Politics and other essays)
Education is not acquiring a stock of ready-made ideas, images, sentiments, beliefs and so forth; it is learning to look, to listen, to think, to feel, to imagine, to believe, to understand, to choose and to wish.
Michael Oakeshott (VOICE OF LIBERAL LEARNING, THE)
Every human being is born an heir to an inheritance to which he can succeed only in the process of learning.
Michael Oakeshott
For words, like Nature, half reveal And half conceal the Soul within.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
From Hobbes’s theory of the sovereign ruling by authority to Max Weber 250 years later, defining the state in terms of a monopoly of force is a slow loss of civil sensitivity. The term “democracy” is strictly a constitutional belief about how authority is generated, but today it most commonly commends rather than names a government that serves some particular interest, such as that of “the people.” The drift of these and other confusions of our political talk has always been to transform the subtle and balanced features attributed to the state in the past into an enterprise that facilitates our political preferences. It would be hard to deny that political sophistication has given way to a kind of partisan brutishness, some elements of which Oakeshott thought had already been recognized by Tocqueville in 1848: “… the passions of man, from being political, have now become social.” And this means that men care now far more about “the satisfaction of substantive wants” and the power of government needed to supply them than about freedom and constitutionality.
Kenneth Minogue
Now, the disposition to be conservative in respect of politics reflects a quite different view of the activity of governing. The man of this disposition understands it to be the business of a government not to inflame passion and give it new objects to feed upon, but to inject into the activities of already too passionate men an ingredient of moderation; to restrain, to deflate, to pacify and to reconcile; not to stoke the fires of desire, but to damp them down. And all this, not because passion is vice and moderation virtue, but because moderation is indispensable if passionate men are to escape being locked in an encounter of mutual frustration.
Michael Oakeshott (Rationalism in Politics and other essays)
England in August 1914 was more of a state than she was during the great industrial strikes of 1911–1912.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
the first rule of Moritz Haupt for interpreting the classics,—‘Man soll nicht übersetzen.’ [‘Do not translate’:
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
To theorize’ means, to see as a whole. The actual is a small part of the whole, or a single aspect of it, which, when taken by itself is, by reason of its incompleteness, both meaningless and comparatively unreal. To see the actual in its wholeness is to see it filled out with all that it implies, supplemented by that which gives it meaning.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
I seat philosophers, statesmen, slaveholders, scribblers, Catholics, fascists, evangelicals, businessmen, racists, and hacks at the same table: Hobbes next to Hayek, Burke across from Palin, Nietzsche in between Ayn Rand and Antonin Scalia, with Adams, Calhoun, Oakeshott, Ronald Reagan, Tocqueville, Theodore Roosevelt, Margaret Thatcher, Ernst Jünger, Carl Schmitt, Winston Churchill, Phyllis Schlafly, Richard Nixon, Irving Kristol, Francis Fukuyama, and George W. Bush interspersed throughout.
Corey Robin (The Reactionary Mind: Conservatism from Edmund Burke to Sarah Palin)
When Mr. Lippmann says that the founders of our free institutions were adherents of the philosophy of natural law, and that ‘the free political institutions of the Western world were conceived and established’ by men who held certain abstract beliefs, he speaks with the shortened perspective of an American way of thinking in which a manner of conducting affairs is inconceivable without an architect and without a premeditated ‘dedication to a proposition.’ But the fact is that nobody ever ‘founded these institutions.’ They are the product of innumerable human choices, over long stretches of time, but not of any human design.
Michael Oakeshott
Take Michael Oakeshott’s famous definition in his essay “On Being Conservative”: “To be conservative, then, is to prefer the familiar to the unknown, to prefer the tried to the untried, fact to mystery, the actual to the possible, the limited to the unbounded, the near to the distant, the sufficient to the superabundant, the convenient to the perfect, present laughter to utopian bliss.” One cannot, it seems, enjoy fact and mystery, near and distant, laughter and bliss. One must choose. Far from affirming a simple hierarchy of preferences, Oakeshott’s either/or signals that we are on existential ground, where the choice is not between something and its opposite but between something and its negation.
Corey Robin (The Reactionary Mind: Conservatism from Edmund Burke to Sarah Palin)
Culture teaches that there is much one does not want to know .
Michael Oakeshott
Browning: ‘Justinian’s Pandects only make precise / What simply sparkled in men’s eyes before’.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
cannot associate with one another without creating a moral relationship.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
Image the whole, then execute the parts— Fancy the fabric Quite, ere you build, ere steel strike fire from quartz Ere mortar dab brick!
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
For there is not so complete and perfect a part that we know of nature, which does not owe the being it has, and the excellence of it, to its neighbours.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
a child might possibly change his country; a man can only wish that he might change it.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
For a great state, qua state, is not one which embraces a great population or an extensive territory, but one which achieves a great intensity of social unity. And in this matter we must bear in mind that unity means unity of purpose and will, and not merely unity of action and result. One of the most significant reasons for refusing to attribute an unlimited degree of statehood to those associations which are legally known as states, is that their size is governed by considerations of commerce, mere whim, or by other limited ends, rather than by reference to the good life or the excellence of souls.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
We should not be surprised therefore if British conservative thinkers – notably Hume, Smith, Burke and Oakeshott – have tended to see no tension between a defence of the free market and a traditionalist vision of social order. For they have put their faith in the spontaneous limits placed on the market by the moral consensus of the community and have seen both the market and the constraints as the work of the same invisible hand. Maybe that moral consensus is now breaking down. But
Roger Scruton (How to Be a Conservative)
We remember the Spartan ambassador who, being asked in whose name he had come, replied: ‘In the name of the State, if I succeed; if I fail, in my own.’ [See Plutarch, ‘Lycurgus’, Lives, tr. J. Langhorne and W. Langhorne (London: Ward, Lock & Co., Limited, nd [1898]), pp. 40–1:
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
The real, if it is anything, is a coherent whole, it is a unity so unified as to preclude the possibility of disunity. And this is what we have called the truth. The real thing is the thing as it truly exists. The true thing, the thing as it exists in its wholeness, is the real thing.[26] And how does this differ from what we have called the ideal? In no respect whatever. The word Hegel uses for ‘wholeness’ is ‘reasonableness’, and if we are content to understand it (and not to abuse it) his assertion that was vernünftig ist, das ist wirklich; und was wirklich ist, das ist vernünftig, is not so wide of the mark.[27] Thought out to the end, as we have tried to do, the ideal not only grows out of the real, not only is contained in the real, but is the real.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
The process of experiencing is well described by Goethe when he says that our life is made up of our connections with the world about us, and that we must each spin our own web and sit at the centre to catch what we can.[21] The web itself is made up of past experiences, and each new connection with the world about us, in so far as it is fully known and understood, is an addition to that web, and so an added means of experiencing.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
So far from a political ideology being the quasi-divine parent of political activity, it turns out to be its earthly stepchild. Instead of an independently premeditated scheme of ends to be pursued, it is a system of ideas abstracted from the manner in which people have been accustomed to go about the business of attending to the arrangements of their societies. The pedigree of every political ideology shows it to be the creature, not of premeditation in advance of political activity, but of meditation upon a manner of politics. In short, political activity comes first and a political ideology follows after; and the understanding of politics we are investigating has the disadvantage of being, in the strict sense, preposterous. Let us consider the matter first in relation to scientific hypothesis, which I have taken to play a role in scientific activity in some respects similar to that of an ideology in politics. If a scientific hypothesis were a self-generated bright idea which owed nothing to scientific activity, then empiricism governed by hypothesis could be considered to compose a self-contained manner of activity; but this certainly is not its character. The truth is that only a man who is already a scientist can formulate a scientific hypothesis; that is, an hypothesis is not an independent invention capable of guiding scientific inquiry, but a dependent supposition which arises as an abstraction from within already existing scientific activity. Moreover, even when the specific hypothesis has in this manner been formulated, it is inoperative as a guide to research without constant reference to the traditions of scientific inquiry from which it was abstracted. The concrete situation does not appear until the specific hypothesis, which is the occasion of empiricism being set to work, is recognized as itself the creature of owing how to conduct a scientific inquiry. Or consider the example of cookery. It might be supposed that an ignorant man, some edible materials, and a cookery book compose together the necessities of a self-moved (or concrete) activity called cooking. But nothing is further from the truth. The cookery book is not an independently generated beginning from which cooking can spring; it is nothing more than an abstract of somebody's knowledge of how to cook: it is the stepchild, not the parent of the activity. The book, in its tum, may help to set a man on to dressing a dinner, but if it were his sole guide he could never, in fact, begin: the book speaks only to those who know already the kind of thing to expect from it and consequently bow to interpret it. Now, just as a cookery book presupposes somebody who knows how to cook, and its use presupposes somebody who already knows how to use it, and just as a scientific hypothesis springs from a knowledge of how to conduct a scientific investigation and separated from that knowledge is powerless to set empiricism profitably to work, so a political ideology must be understood, not as an independently premeditated beginning for political activity, but as knowledge (abstract and generalized) of a concrete manner of attending to the arrangements of a society. The catechism which sets out the purposes to be pursued merely abridges a concrete manner of behaviour in which those purposes are already hidden. It does not exist in advance of political activity, and by itself it is always an insufficient guide. Political enterprises, the ends to be pursued, the arrangements to be established (all the normal ingredients of a political ideology), cannot be premeditated in advance of a manner of attending to the arrangements of a society; what we do, and moreover what we want to do, is the creature of how we are accustomed to conduct our affairs. Indeed, it often reflects no more than a dis­covered ability to do something which is then translated into an authority to do it.
Michael Oakeshott (Rationalism in Politics and other essays)
If we’re not careful, the automation of mental labor, by changing the nature and focus of intellectual endeavor, may end up eroding one of the foundations of culture itself: our desire to understand the world. Predictive algorithms may be supernaturally skilled at discovering correlations, but they’re indifferent to the underlying causes of traits and phenomena. Yet it’s the deciphering of causation—the meticulous untangling of how and why things work the way they do—that extends the reach of human understanding and ultimately gives meaning to our search for knowledge. If we come to see automated calculations of probability as sufficient for our professional and social purposes, we risk losing or at least weakening our desire and motivation to seek explanations, to venture down the circuitous paths that lead toward wisdom and wonder. Why bother, if a computer can spit out “the answer” in a millisecond or two? In his 1947 essay “Rationalism in Politics,” the British philosopher Michael Oakeshott provided a vivid description of the modern rationalist: “His mind has no atmosphere, no changes of season and temperature; his intellectual processes, so far as possible, are insulated from all external influence and go on in the void.” The rationalist has no concern for culture or history; he neither cultivates nor displays a personal perspective. His thinking is notable only for “the rapidity with which he reduces the tangle and variety of experience” into “a formula.”54 Oakeshott’s words also provide us with a perfect description of computer intelligence: eminently practical and productive and entirely lacking in curiosity,
Nicholas Carr (The Glass Cage: Where Automation is Taking Us)
The conduct of affairs, for the Rationalist, is a matter of solving problems, and in this no man can hope to be successful whose reason has become inflexible by surrender to habit or is clouded by the fumes of tradition. In this activity the character which the Rationalist claims for himself is the character of the engineer, whose mind (it is supposed) is controlled throughout by appropriate technique and whose first step is to dismiss from his attention everything not directly related to his specific intentions. The assimilation of politics to engineering is, indeed, what may be called the myth of rationalist politics. And it is, of course, a recurring theme in the literature of Rationalism. The politics it inspires may be called the politics of the felt need; for the Rationalist, politics are always charged with the feeling of the moment. He waits upon circumstance to provide him with his problems, but rejects its aid in their solution. That anything should be allowed to stand between a society and the satisfaction of the felt needs of each moment in its history must appear to the Rationalist a piece of mysticism and nonsense. And his politics are, in fact, the rational solution of those practical conundrums which the recognition of the sovereignty of the felt need perpetually creates in the life of a society. Thus, political life is resolved into a succession of crises, each to be surmounted by the application of "reason." Each generation, indeed, each administration, should see unrolled before it the blank sheet of infinite possibility. And if by chance this tablula vasa has been defaced by the irrational scribblings of tradition-ridden ancestors, then the first task of the Rationalist must be to scrub it clean; as Voltaire remarked, the only way to have good laws is to burn all existing laws and start afresh.
Michael Oakeshott (Rationalism in Politics and other essays)
An ideal society, properly so-called, can be none other than an actual, present, society taken at its truest and best.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
It is agreeable to imagine a future in which the tiresome ‘analytic–Continental split’ is looked back upon as an unfortunate, temporary breakdown of communication – a future in which Sellars and Habermas, Davidson and Gadamer, Putnam and Derrida, Rawls and Foucault, are seen as fellow-travelers on the same journey, fellow-citizens of what Michael Oakeshott called a civitas pelegrina. (Rorty 1997a, pp. 11–12)
Richard J. Bernstein (The Pragmatic Turn)
bonfire, the field was dark, little tendrils of fog drifting through the crowd. I could only dimly make out the shadow of the pavilion behind the fire, and the girls crowding in front of it looked like scribbles on a page. I could not even see the trees on the far edge of the pitch that led into Oakeshott Woods, although I knew they were there. I breathed out and my breath misted in front of me.
Robin Stevens (Jolly Foul Play (Murder Most Unladylike, #4))
Frédéric Dard, Libanius Antiochus, Michael Oakeshott, John Gray, Ammianus Marcellinus, Ibn Battuta, Saadia Gaon, or Joseph de Maistre; he
Nassim Nicholas Taleb (Skin in the Game: Hidden Asymmetries in Daily Life (Incerto))
Strength we think to be a virtue in government, but we do not find our defense against disintegration either in arbitrary or in very great power. Indeed, we are inclined to see in both these the symptoms of an already advanced decay
Michael Oakeshott
The pursuit of perfection is far too important to be handed over to the control and direction of a set of people who by blood, force or election have acquired the right to call themselves 'governors'.
Michael Oakeshott (The Politics of Faith and the Politics of Scepticism (Selected Writings of Michael Oakeshott))
The English philosopher Michael Oakeshott notes that one of the signs of being cold today is that one knows what one doesn't have to know.
Joseph Epstein
The rule of law bakes no bread, it is unable to distribute loaves or fishes (it has none), and it cannot protect itself against external assault, but it re- mains the most civilized and least burdensome conception of a state yet to be devised. —Michael Oakeshott, 19831
Thomas Carothers (Promoting the Rule of Law Abroad: In Search of Knowledge)
To be educated is to know how much one wishes to know and to have the courage not to be tempted beyond this limit .
Michael Oakeshott
Even reason is individualized, and becomes merely the reasoning of an individual without power or authority to oblige acceptance by others: to convince a man is not to enjoy a common understanding with him, but to displace his reason by yours.111
Michael Oakeshott (Hobbes on Civil Association)
Memory is not history, even though memories may be among the evidence a historian examines in constructing a historical past.
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
Memoirs, as everyone knows, make bad history.
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
For history and for science facts are self-evident and are the subject-matter of these studies, but for philosophy they are the most puzzling things imaginable, and when they are really discovered its part is played.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
The demand for moral uniformity is more often practical than theoretical, a demand for moral certainty where none is possible. It is, for Oakeshott, an essentially religious demand, and although an individual agent can seek absolutely reliable guidance in faith, this is not an option that is available to the theorist.
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
it is the historian's job to find coherence in the past, nothing in history can be regarded as accidental. For accident-mere chance or "fortune"-explains nothing, and a past composed of accidents is as unhistorical as a past of necessary consequences.
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
No oak trees without acorns' may be a formally true proposition, but that this acorn did in fact produce this oak tree, there and then, is not a teleological necessity; it is a circumstantial occurrence" (OH 104-5). Because history is what happened, not what must have happened, there is no room in an authentic historical explanation for teleological causes.
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
the issue in historical explanation is to explain the character and not the mere occurrence of events. A historical event is not an atomic, isolated, permanent thing but (as we have seen) an "identity" or "historical individual" constructed by the historian.
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
Empirical reality becomes nature when we view it with respect to its universal characteristics; it becomes history when we view it as particular and individual.
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
practices are displayed only in performances: a practice is the trace, the residue, of its performances. Practices are not "stable compositions of easily recognized characteristics." They are nothing more than "footprints left behind by agents responding to their emergent situations, footprints which are only somewhat less evanescent than the transactions in which they emerged" (OHC ioo).
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
When Plutarch says that a city might sooner subsist without a geographical site than without belief in the gods, his words would not have appeared strange to his countrymen at any time.’]
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
The degeneration of conversation into monologue, dogmatic assertion, is barbarism.
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
To define a thing is to see it clearly, to see it as distinct from other things and at the same time to see its exact relationship with other things: for a thing is its relations and activities.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
to see a thing completely is to set it in relation with the universe.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
In Oakeshott's view, ideas like natural law, fundamental values, basic rights, and "justice as fairness" are detrimental to the rule of law: "more often than not they are the occasion of profitless dispute, and when invoked as the conditions of the obligation to observe the conditions prescribed by lex they positively pervert the association: they are the recipe for anarchy" (OH 16o).
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
Conversation itself has rules, which is why the conversationalist who insists that others must speak his language is a boor. To have a voice of one's own is to acknowledge other voices.
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
Who I am depends not only on what I believe but on the beliefs embedded in the practices of the various communities to which I belong and in terms of which I define my identity.
Terry Nardin (The Philosophy of Michael Oakeshott)
to think nothing about the opinion of his society (if he be in any sense a member) is to be unconsciously influenced by it.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
Hobbes is not an absolutist precisely because he is an authoritarian. His scepticism about the power of reasoning, which applied no less to the ‘artificial reason’ of the Sovereign than to the reasoning of the natural man, together with the rest of his individualism, separate him from the rationalist dictators of his or any age. Indeed, Hobbes, without being himself a liberal, had in him more of the philosophy of liberalism than most of its professed defenders
Efraim Podoksik (The Cambridge Companion to Oakeshott)
Oakeshott believed that civil association has been increasingly displaced by enterprise, under pressure from political elites, managers, parties and ideologues. It is not only socialists with their goals of equality and social justice who have contributed to this displacement. The liberal attempt to adopt the contours of an abstract and universal idea of justice and human rights; the supposedly conservative pursuit of economic growth as the root of social order and the goal of government – these too have a tendency to displace civil association with a new kind of political practice, in which the institutions of society are bent towards a goal that may be incompatible with their inner dynamic. The distinction between civil and enterprise association is not hard and fast: many of our social spheres partake of both arrangements. Nevertheless, it is hard to deny that enterprise tends in a different direction from ordinary forms of community. In enterprise there are instructions coming down from above; there are rivalries and rebellions; there is ruinous failure as well as temporary success. The whole depends on a forward-going energy that must be constantly maintained if things are not to fragment and fall apart. Hence the invocations of ‘progress’, of ‘growth’, of constant ‘advance’ towards the goal which, however, must remain always somewhere in the future, lest the dedication of the citizens cease to be renewed by it.
Roger Scruton (How to Be a Conservative)
potestas is specific, auctoritas is extendable and can grow.
Michael Oakeshott (Lectures in the History of Political Thought (Michael Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 1))
Oakeshott believed that civil association has been increasingly displaced by enterprise, under pressure from political elites, managers, parties and ideologues. It is not only socialists with their goals of equality and social justice who have contributed to this displacement. The liberal attempt to adopt the contours of an abstract and universal idea of justice and human rights; the supposedly conservative pursuit of economic growth as the root of social order and the goal of government – these too have a tendency to displace civil association with a new kind of political practice, in which the institutions of society are bent towards a goal that may be incompatible with their inner dynamic.
Roger Scruton (How to Be a Conservative)
Property was thus appall’d / That the self was not the same / Single nature’s double name / Neither two nor one was call’d.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
in modern philosophy, the first glimpse of the true view of the conception of ‘might is right’ as applying to government is to be found in the political writings of Spinoza. Briefly it is this. Government, as such, has a limited sphere of activity. This limitation is self-limitation; and the proper province of government comprehends all that it is able to accomplish. Government may not attempt that which it is unable to achieve; that which it is able to achieve is its true and proper sphere of action. Ask and answer the question, What can government do? and we have solved the problem of what it ought to do, that is, we have defined its limits and discovered its particular nature. Its might is its right.
Michael Oakeshott (Early Political Writings 1925–30: A discussion of some matters preliminary to the study of political philosophy' and 'The philosophical approach to politics ... Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 5))
A single homogenous line of development is to be found in history only if history is made a dummy upon which to practise the skill of a ventriloquist.
Michael Oakeshott (The Politics of Faith and the Politics of Scepticism (Selected Writings of Michael Oakeshott))
The rule of law, properly speaking, is an exercise of authority in which the power of the subjects of that authority to seek and to obtain the satisfaction of their desires is qualified by the obligation to subscribe to certain moral-procedural conditions while leaving them to choose prudentially for themselves the substantive actions and utterances in which to seek such satisfactions.
Michael Oakeshott (What Is History?: Selected Writings (Michael Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 2))
History has two main elements—(i) Events in time, and (ii) the recollection of these events in the mind. Both of these are, I think, essential.
Michael Oakeshott (What Is History?: Selected Writings (Michael Oakeshott Selected Writings Book 2))
We are acquisitive to the point of greed; ready to drop the bone we have for its reflection magnified in the mirror of the future.
Michael Oakeshott
When we are young we are not disposed to make concessions to the world; we never feel the balance of a thing in ourhands - unless it be a cricket bat. We are not apt to distinguish between our liking and our esteem; urgency is our criterion of importance; and we do not easily understand that what is humdrum need not be despicable.
Michael Oakeshott (On being conservative)
(The conservative) will be suspicious of proposals for change in excess of what the situation calls for, of rulers who demand extra-ordinary powers in order to make great changes and whose utterances are tied to generalities like “the public good” or “social justice”, and of Saviours of Society who buckle on armor and seek dragons to slay
Michael Oakeshott (On being conservative)
In any generation, even the most revolutionary, the arrangements which are enjoyed always far exceed those which are recognized to stand in need of attention, and those which are being prepared for enjoyment are few in comparison with those which receive amendment: the new is an insignificant proportion of the whole.
Corey Abel (The Meanings of Michael Oakeshott's Conservatism (British Idealist Studies 1: Oakeshott Book 3))
any case, Oakeshott found he could enjoy the world, in spite of living ‘after Auschwitz’ and in the midst of ‘the crisis of modernity.
Corey Abel (The Meanings of Michael Oakeshott's Conservatism (British Idealist Studies 1: Oakeshott Book 3))
When we are young we are not disposed tomake concessions to the world; we never feel the balance of a thing in ourhands - unless it be a cricket bat. We are not apt to distinguish between ourliking and our esteem; urgency is our criterion of importance; and we do not easily understand that what is humdrum need not be despicable.
Michael Oakeshott (On being conservative)
But a man's identity (or that of a community) is nothing more than an unbroken rehearsal of contingencies, each at the mercy of circumstance and each significant in proportion to its familiarity.
Michael Oakeshott
The British philosopher Michael Oakeshott was issuing a useful warning against hubris when he wrote, “In political activity, then, men sail a boundless and bottomless sea; there is neither harbor for shelter nor floor for anchorage, neither starting place nor appointed destination. The enterprise is to keep afloat on an even keel; the sea is both friend and enemy; and the seamanship consists in using the resources of a traditional manner of behavior in order to make a friend of every hostile occasion.
David Brooks (The Social Animal: The Hidden Sources Of Love, Character, And Achievement)
a man's identity (or that of a community) is nothing more than an unbroken rehearsal of contingencies, each at the mercy of circumstance and each significant in proportion to its familiarity.
Michael Oakeshott
art is question without answer; religion is question and answer, where the answer cannot be explained but only repeated; science is question and answer, where the answer can be explained in other terms but is abstract, universal and does not deal with particulars; and history is question and answer, where the answer is concrete and particular, but where the totality of answers about particulars can never be assembled.
Efraim Podoksik (The Cambridge Companion to Oakeshott)
Live with your age, but be not its creation; labour for your contemporaries, but do for them what they need, and not what they praise’. F. Schiller, Aesthetical and Philosophical Essays (Boston: Francis A. Niccolls, 1902), p. 33.
Efraim Podoksik (The Cambridge Companion to Oakeshott)